19 Matching Annotations
  1. May 2016
    1. But generalized trigger warnings aren't so much about helping people with PTSD as they are about a certain kind of performative feminism: they're a low-stakes way to use the right language to identify yourself as conscious of social justice issues. Even better is demanding a trigger warning – that identifies you as even more aware, even more feminist, even more solicitous than the person who failed to adequately provide such a warning.

      On what basis are we to accept this claim? Is this simply grounded in anecdotal evidence?

    1. simplistic, coddling warnings are a terrible idea

      I agree that simplistic warnings are not a good idea, but that is because I believe they are not sufficiently responsive to the moral reasons in favor of providing advanced warning.

    1. Are supporters of trigger warnings just hoping to give kids a few more years of refuge from the outside world? Or do they somehow think that these policies might spark the outside world to change?

      Neither!

    2. you could make this same argument about a lot of things. But in other cases—for example, a university policy aimed at racism or disabilities or whatnot—it would presumably be done in the hope that it might influence public policy and eventually lead to changes in the wider world. But does anyone have this hope for trigger warnings?

      I do not accept that the use of trigger warnings by professors ought to be done "in the hope that it might influence public policy."

    3. What I don't get is what anyone thinks the point of this is. You're never going to have trigger warnings in ordinary life, right? So even if universities started adopting broad trigger policies, it would accomplish nothing except to semi-protect sensitive students for a few more years of their lives, instead of teaching them how to deal with upsetting material.

      There is an answer to Drum's question: viz., that carefully crafted and delivered trigger warnings can help students learn by preventing them from disengaging.

    1. The standard critique here is that a "trigger warning" policy written like that would impinge on academic freedom, chill speech, and infantalize 18, 19, 20, and 21-year-olds.
    2. The Oberlin language is broad enough to cover a huge chunk of network TV shows, hip hop albums, standup comics and Hollywood films.

      This raises the issue of the scope of any alleged obligation to warn about potentially triggering material.

    3. "Trigger warnings," by whatever name, are diminished when applied to extreme content that a typical person expects, or when used so ubiquitously that we reflexively ignore the meaningless tip because it isn't specific enough to be useful.
    1. prescriptive reading

      Kang raises an interesting point about trigger-warnings; viz., that they prescribe reading texts in a certain way, much like his professor's comment about Lolita prescribed reading it in a particular way.

      I'm not sure what I think about this as a general claim. I imagine that this may be true in certain cases, but not in others. It is also important to note that even if we accept the truth of this claim, it doesn't immediately follow that this is a criticism of the practice.

  2. Apr 2016
  3. Mar 2016
    1. This image, by Jean-Jacques Henner, shows Jesus in a posture of repose but not swaddled in burial shrouds. It shows him all alone, without any company– no angels, no grieving family, and pictured against a dark background.

      Henner's painting could've just as easily been titled, "The Harrowing of Hades." What is the descent into Hell, but God "experiencing"—extending God's self into, being made subject to—the nonbeing that is death? I don't conceive of God's descent into Hell as anything other than God really, truly (yet paradoxically) being subject to the separation from God, which is (or we should say: was) death. This is perhaps the aspect of the good news that is more paradoxical than even the God-Man: it is the death of God, which thereby conquers death, for death is now not beyond God. And those who have died are now not separated from God; the incarnate God has shared in the same.

  4. Dec 2015
    1. He argues that transubstantiation is an example of an doctrine that cannot be confirmed by a miracle because it is "contrary to sense." In other words, the thing proposed contradicts what is given by sense observation. The question will be whether this is because something which contradicts the senses is impossible or whether it is because one cannot justifiably believe the thing for some other reason. I suspect it is the latter.

    2. Tillotson asserts that miracles constitute the chief "external proof" or evidence in favor of the "divinity" of Christian doctrines. (Notice that he doesn't put it in terms of "truth.")

    1. This is a great illustration; we can easily see how the repetition would allow her to be (re)acquainted, so to speak, with the traumatic moment, but in a way that would allow her to experience it from the other perspective.