3,077 Matching Annotations
  1. Mar 2022
    1. Given the abundance of evidence on persistence ofpatrimonial rule despite rotation of parties in power, it is tempting to speak of aMosca-type of “political class”that in most countries of Latin America is squarelylocated within the patrimonial democratic quadrant.

      patrimonial democracy

    2. The A/E framework has important advantages as a source for theory building. It ismore able than the QOD approach to articulate new hypotheses about the causes ofthe low quality of political institutions in Latin America, as well as to mobilize oldbut valuable insights that had been overlooked by the democratization-centeredvision of regional politics

      A/E > QOD

    3. Chile between1990 and 1998 had elements of the expanded definition of democracy but did notmeet the minimal one.

      it did not meet the minimum due to senadores vitalicios

    4. Correlation between access and exercise across three databases

      correlation between access and exercise of power for normal middle income countries is .59, which assumes a modest correlation between higher access to power leading to a higher exercise of power. In LatAm, this correlation is -0.08

    5. Similarly, by defining democracy as a specific regime of access, the A/Eframework enhances the precision of the standard Shumpeterian definition andmakes unnecessary what has been the most common patch to it. Taking into accountthe existence of “tutelary powers”in Chile that over the 1990s constrained theinfluence of democratically elected presidents and representatives, scholars havefound it useful to add to the Shumpeterian attributes the condition that electionsgrant real power to those elected.11 When democracy is defined as a form of accessto state power, the patch becomes redundant. Power is already present in thedefinition of regime, and it logically carries over into the definition of the democratictype. According to the A/E framework, if elections do not grant access to statepower, they are not part of the political regime

      if elections do not grant access to state power, then they are not a part of the political regime

    6. The last set of decisions in the A/E framework includes the definition of “regime”in terms of access and “administration”in terms of exercise. Regime andadministration, in turn, provide the overarching concept for the polar types ofauthoritarianism versus democracy and patrimonialism versus bureaucracy, respec-tively. I

      patrimonialism is the opposite of bureaucracy

    7. The central claim of this paper is that the A/E framework provides a usefulalternative to the QOD approach for the purposes of creating and testing causalhypotheses about systematic abuses of political power—in new democracies, olddemocracies, or authoritarian regimes

      A/E vs QOD

    8. he access to political power and the exerciseof political power are simply two analytically distinct aspects of the institutionalstructure of the modern territorial state. In all societies where the means of coercionare concentrated in the state, positions in the state become a key source of power.Relations between state and society can then be naturally grouped into twocategories. One, running upwards from the society to the state, involves the efforts ofgroups in society to gain control over state positions—the access side of politics.The other, running downwards from the state to society, refers to the use of politicalpower to align the behavior of social groups with the order created by the state—theexercise side.

      society-government interplay

    9. erspective, these cases do not count as high- or low-qualitydemocracies for the obvious reason that they are not democracies in the first place.Nevertheless, they are useful comparative references because they are a source ofdata about the forces behind changes in informal political institutions, including themotivations of rulers who reduced abuses of their own power. F

      authoritarian regimes can often exercise institutional power in the name of economic growth; however, it is highly variable when exercised

    10. Scholarly definitions, like the expanded definition of democracy, are analytical toolscrafted to achieve research goals. Therefore, they can only be judged in terms oftheir effectiveness in achieving such goals.

      excessively thick definitions of democracy

    11. To recapitulate, the premise that deficits of institutional quality are problems ofdemocratization has led the third generation of democratization studies to adopt anexpanded definition of democracy. The current scholarship on democratizationfocuses on the countries that have completed the transition (i.e., that meet theminimalist definition), and differentiates them in terms of levels of QOD based onthe degree to which the additional attributes of the expanded definition are present.The distinction between democratic regime and democratic state, an example of thegeneric distinction between the minimalist and the expanded definition ofdemocracy, is meant to provide two benchmarks—a lower one and a higher one—to assess achievements and failures in the process of democratization.

      two benchmarks for democracy (a lower benchmark and then a qualitative one)

    12. Robert Dahl’s definition of polyarchy as the firstbenchmark of democracy, which includes free elections, universal suffrage, and theset of civil and political liberties required to ensure a fair competition for positions ingovernment, e.g., free press and associational rights (Dahl 1971: 3 —6). Thisbenchmark has allowed the first generation of democratization studies to distinguishcountries that completed the transition from those that did not.

      Robert Dahl benchmark for democracy

    13. Although Latin American countries have completed the transitionto democracy, they are not fully democratized.

      not fully democratized but in the process of doing so

    14. might be more productive to conceptualize them asseparate processes than to subsume them as components of the same macro-process, that is, as integral parts of democratization

      institutions and the transition itself should be separated

    15. Infact, in most Latin American countries, the main defenders and beneficiaries ofdemocratic transitions—mass parties and the “political class”—are in generalinimical to changes in the form of exercise

      often even populists are anti changes in forms of institutional power

    16. The very premise of the current diagnosis is thatproblems in the so-called quality of democracy (QOD) are deficiencies in thedemocratization process. In fact, both scholarly and policy analysts have embracedthe QOD as the central motivation and topic of a third generation of democratizationstudies, which is seen as succeeding the first generation centered on “transitions”(the collapse of dictatorships and the rise of democratic regimes) and the secondgeneration referred to issues of “consolidation”(variations in the probabilities that anewly democratic regime will survive into the foreseeable future).

      QOD=quality of democracies

    17. Mostgovernments in Latin America are the genuine product of free and inclusiveelections, but few resist the temptation of abusing the political power that theelectoral process has granted them

      access is less so the issue with Latin American democracies

    18. Costa Rica, Chile, and Uruguay.

      why these three?

    19. Most new democracies are “low quality”democracies. Such is the unanimousdiagnosis of the current generation of studies on comparative democratization.Corruption, government by executive decree, clientelism, and ineffective checks andbalances are listed as the most prominent individual symptoms of the alleged deficitin democratic quality.1 In Latin America, several new democracies seem to have thefull syndrome.

      In Latin America, new democracies have challenge with exercising institutional power

    20. ereas regimetransitions are changes in the form of access to power, problems of institutionalquality involve the exercise of power.

      transitions involve access to power, institutional quality more pertains to the exercise of power

    Annotators

  2. www-jstor-org.proxy.uchicago.edu www-jstor-org.proxy.uchicago.edu
    1. Homo sapiens exhibit only moderate sexual dimorphism in stature, weight, and many skeletal features, including the dentition. But humans are strik-ingly dimorphic in certain epigamic features. Postpubertal males typically have more hirsute faces and bodies; their pates commonly bald progressively with age. Human females are more glabrous, usually keep their head hair, and have special fat depots in their breasts, hips, and thighs that make them more curvaceous than the common man (Figure 2.17).1

      male and female differences

    2. Chimpanzee skulls are much less sexually dimorphic than those of gorillas and orangutans, though the diff erence appears quite early in development.13

      chimpanzee skulls are less sexually dimorphic than those of gorillas and orangutans

    3. Like people, chimpanzees and bonobos are moderately sexually dimor-phic in body size

      chimpanzees and bonobos only moderately sexually dimorphic

    4. h ereafter, male secondary sexual charac-teristics, namely, their massive cranial superstructures, elongate palates and mandibles, large canine teeth, and a distinctive fi brofatty pad over the poste-rior part of the sagittal crest, develop rather rapidly (Figure 2.13).1

      male secondary sex characteristics of gorillas

    5. Ecologically, chimpanzees are the most versatile of the extant apes, which might have characterized them for many centuries or millennia.118 Th ey in-habit a remarkable variety of primary and secondary forests, deciduous wood-lands, riverine forests, and forest- savanna ecotonal regions, extending from the Gambia and Guinea- Bissau through West and northern Central Africa to western Uganda and northwestern Tanzania (Map 2.2).119 Most long- term studies of free chimpanzees are situated in more open canopy locations in-stead of closed- canopy rain forests.120 Two upper central incisors and an M1 from Middle Pleistocene deposits of the Kapthurin Formation, Tugen Hills, Central Kenya, indicate that >545 Ka, chimpanzees were penecontempora-neous with Homo sp.

      chimpanzees are ecologically versatile

    6. Ungar observed that Suma-tran orangutans often employed their incisors to nip or crush hard, brittle fruits and to ingest arthropods, fl owers, stems, and leaves.

      orangutan teeth are useful for hard and brittle consumption

    7. Orangutans are extremely sexually dimorphic in body mass but less so in canine height.

      orangutans are sexually dimorphic in body mass but not canine height

    8. Although males are commonly somewhat heavier than females, some adult females outweigh conspecifi c adult males. Th e lesser apes evidence minimal sexual dimorphism in body size, cranial features, and canine tooth dimensions, but they exhibit sexual dimorphism in some overall body dimensions, and several hylobatid species are dramatically dimorphic

      sexual dimorphism in lesser apes is variable

    9. Anthropologists and human biologists have failed dismally in their at-tempts to subdivide Homo sapiens into subspecies (called races) largely because of the prehistoric and historical global admixture among the great variety of people who grace the planet and the disagreements on which features should be used to classify them.56 Indeed, some argue that the exercise is not only futile but also unethical: past and current abuses of individuals and ethnic groups have been premised on narrowly conceived featural and folk racial classifi cations

      race in humans is a flawed concept as we have a lot of cross-regional contact; perhaps this is an ingredient for success as a species that could be used in the midterm

    10. n view of the many ambiguities and uncertainties about how to interpret the molecular ge ne tic data, for extant Hominoidea I employ a possibly gradis-tic four- family scheme, in which Hominidae is reserved for culturally depen-dent, ecologically specialized humans and their bipedal ancestors; Panidae comprises the African great apes (gorillas, chimpanzees, and bonobos); Pon-gidae includes the orangutans; and the gibbons aggregate in the Hylobatidae (Table 2.3).5

      new heuristic that divides this hominoidea community into humans; panidae (great apes); pongidae; and hylobitidae

    11. We do not know how many genes mark levels of separation among apes and people.• We cannot discretely recognize their phenotypic expressions.• Th ey probably are not of equal value to sort people from apes and apes from other apes.41

      limitations currently in the field of ape(?)ology

    12. genome indicate 97 percent average and median identity be-tween orangutan and human versus 99 percent identity between chimpanzee and human. I

      chimpanzee and human lexical similarity of 99 percent in dna

    13. “lesser ape” refers only to the fact that they are much smaller than bonobos, chimpanzees, gorillas, and orangutans, not that they are of dimin-ished importance in the animal kingdom

      lesser apes are smaller in size than great apes

    14. Traditionally, the Pongidae or pongid apes included orangutans ( Pongo spp.), chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes), bonobos (Pan paniscus), and gorillas (Go-rilla spp.), known collectively as the great apes, and numerous fossil forms. Th ey have in common a diploid chromosome number (symbolized 2n) of 48 (versus 2n 46 in Homo sapiens), the habit of nest building, and many anatomi-cal, physiological, and biomolecular features.

      Pongid apes (orangutans and gorillas) have common diploid chromosomes (48, 1 pair more than humans), build habits of nest buildings and have similar biomolecular features to humans

    15. Traditionally, the Primates were divided into two suborders: the Prosimii and the Anthropoidea. Th e extant prosimians include the bizarre aye- aye and the tooth- combed lemurs, lorises, and galagos. Th e Anthropoidea encompasses all extant monkeys, apes, and humans and their fossil collaterals and intermedi-ate forms

      promisians versus anthropoidea: promisians-lemurs anthropoidea-apes and humans

    16. If one wishes to highlight people, the proper phrasings would be “human and nonhuman primate evolution” and “humans and other animals.”

      humans and nonhuman primate evolution or other phrases for specificity

    1. "p1: democracy is second nature to them"

      institutions make all the difference

      p8: encomienda system--> main roadmap for settlement. Most Spanish conquest revolved around plunder. P9: "strategy and institutions of conquest perfected in Mexico adopted everywhere else"

      P13: location of mitas determined development and prosperity (Calca vs Acomayo)

      P15: English and Jamestown forced to be inventive due to limiations

      P20: martial law in Jamestown and forcing people to work for survival, relying on their own labor. Incentives to invest and work hard were essential to survival

      P23: collapse of rigid systems in Maryland and North Carolina

      P27: Mexico insecurity and lack of stable presidencies led to the government being unable to embrace industiral revolution and inventions.

      P28: role and spread of patenting

      P29: struggles w Mexican banking system

      P35: Carolis Slim vs Bill Gates

      P36: recurso de amparo protocol to be an exception to the rule

    Annotators

    1. This was again an example of the bottom-up creationof a new discourse by societal actors, demonstrating society’s contributionin changing ethnicity regimes

      see? This isn't just one anti-elite person

    2. Yeltsin’s presidency brought to power a counterelite, which repudiatedSoviet policies and represented ethnic constituencies harmed by passport eth-nicity, including Russian Jews. Jews were disproportionately represented inYeltsin’s governments and among his advisors in larger numbers than has everbeen the case in Soviet governments in the postwar era, and Jews stronglysupported Yeltsin throughout his rule.108 Of the Jewish members of Yeltsin’sgovernments, Yevgeny Sapiro, as Minister of Nationalities, and Emil Pain, as anAdviser on Interethnic and Regional Problems, took on responsibilities directlylinked to the role of ethnicity in state-society relations

      counter-elites

    3. Therefore, not a razor-thin majority but a wide margin of power andpolitical hegemony is necessary for overcoming resistance and bringing aboutethnic regime change

      need a lot of power

    4. Counterelites provide the actors with the motivation, interests, and preferencesnecessary to initiate a reform, in order to satisfy their constituencies who havegrievances against the status quo. The new discourse on ethnicity and nation-ality performs multiple indispensable functions: it provides the ideas and thecognitive frame necessary for action, and a new vision of the nation with whichto counter the defenders of the status quo in debates and propaganda.

      role of counter-elites

    5. Issues of membership, such as citizenship andimmigration, would occupy the center stage in monoethnic regimes, becausepeople who do not share the titular ethnic background are excluded frommembership. One would expect issues of expression to occupy the center stagein antiethnic regimes, where membership is ethnically diverse but institutionalexpression of ethnic diversity is not allowed. One would expect the ethnicallyspecific allocations to occupy the center stage in multiethnic regimes, whereethnic diversity is already given institutional expression.

      contestable policies by ethnic group policy

    6. Expression of ethnic differences was paramount. The USSR was structuredas a multiethnic federation. The Soviet constitution mentioned dozens of ethniccategories, together constituting the USSR. There were 191 ethnic categoriescodified in the census of 1926 and recorded in internal passports issued to indi-vidual citize

      isn't this still limited to some extent?

    7. The Soviet Union was the leading example of a multiethnic regime in theworld. The extent of multiethnic recognition and institutionalization achievedin the USSR was unprecedented. Just as Germany stood for a particularlymonoethnic formula for modern nationhood, the USSR was the model for amultiethnic political community. Membership was not ethnically restricted andneither was there ethnic-priority immigration. There were no ethnic “minori-ties,” because all ethnicities together constituted the Soviet peopl

      no minorities in soviet union, but ethnically divided

    8. In the Soviet case, thereis only one source suggesting that Yuri Andropov, who led the USSR forfifteen months during 1982–1983, entertained the idea of abolishing ethnicfederalism by reorganizing the Soviet Union as a nonethnic federal state.28Even if one believes that Andropov entertained such an idea, which I do, it isclear that such a singular episode pales in comparison to the repeated effortsaround removing ethnicity from the internal passport.

      single leaders cannot usually change ethnicity ideals for an entire state

    9. These instances of change and continuity demonstrate theextreme difficulty to change state policies on ethnicity; even the alignment ofthe proverbial stars – counterelites, new discourses, and hegemonic power –only sufficed to change one significant state policy on ethnicity. Even the excep-tional coincidence of three conditions for change in state policies on ethnicitymight not be enough for a wholesale ethnic regime change that encompassesall or most state policies on ethnicity

      very gradual, even in the german case

    10. Turkeyestablished new public television stations broadcasting exclusively in Kurdishand Arabic, which is a movement away from an antiethnic toward a multiethnicregime, but Turkey did not become an ethnofederal state, and other featuresof an antiethnic regime remained. What does the limited nature of the change,limited in each case to one policy area, suggest about regimes of ethnicity

      limited changes in countries on ethnicity policy

    11. Max Weber’s definition of ethnicity as “subjective belief in commondescent” is the best definition of ethnicity insofar as it distinguishesethnic from religious, linguistic, economic, ideological, and other socia

      weber basis

    12. This new conceptualization connects the study of nation building to studies ofethnic diversity and citizenship, while providing a coherent typology of statepolicies on ethnicity that accommodates the full range of variation across cases

      purpose of paper

    13. However, “passport ethnicity” also made possible the deportation ofall ethnic Germans, Chechens, Crimean Tatars, and other ethnic groups, result-ing in the decimation of their populations.12 Passport ethnicity was also usedto discriminate against Jews in politics and employment. Attempts to removeethnicity from the passport since the 1950s failed. Even after the dissolutionof the USSR, ethnicity was preserved in the internal passports of almost allthe post-Soviet states.13 Yet in 1997, ethnicity was removed from the Russianinternal passport. How did such a historic change occur?

      internal passport system

    14. This book explains the dynamics of persistence and change in state policiestoward ethnicity. How do state policies that regulate the relationship betweenethnicity and nationality change

      how does one gain citizenship?

    Annotators

  3. Feb 2022
    1. Unlike Gellner or Anderson, who emphasize the importance of industriali-zation and print capitalism for the spread of nationalism, or Kedourie andKohn, who highlight the causal priority of willful idealism in the process, Ihold that the emergence of nationalism is the result of an interaction betweenstrategic choices made under the structural conditions of international com-petition for territory and resources within the Westphalian system of states, onthe one hand, and the technological innovations

      compared to other literature

    2. “Ethnicity”matters, butonly when it is activated in the international arena.

      ethnicity vs non core is different but ethnicity can be played on

    3. A non-core group supported by anenemy external power and residing in a revisionist host state is more likely to beexcluded than targeted with assimilation or accommodation; if a similar groupwere to reside in a status quo state, it would most likely be targeted withassimilationist policies; taking the form of colonization by core group membersand internal displacement of non-core group members. Finally, non-core groupssupported by allied states are more likely to be accommodated than be assimi-lated or exclu

      different methods

    4. I argued that ahost state’s foreign policy goals, as well as its interstate relations with externalpowers that may be supporting its non-core groups, drive nation-buildingchoices.

      summary

    5. Why would an allied power support a non-core group? Often states cultivaterelations with non-core groups abroad for economic reasons. For example,following World War I, Romania kept ties with Vlachs living in Greece –anally at the time. In an article published in a Romanian newspaper, RenastereaRomana, by one of its chief editors we find out that Romania is cultivating theseties “not just because of feelings toward Romanians beyond the Danube Riverbut also because of economic considerations, since these Romanians are verybright, hard working, and phenomenal merchants.”105 Alliances do change andthe links that have developed between a non-core group and an external powerare sometimes hard to sever.

      sometimes links can be peaceful

    6. All non-core groups are potential targets for mobilization and support byexternal powers.

      all non-core groups are international targets in the age of nationalism

    7. ally, a host state is likely to pursue assimilation through internalcolonization if the state favors the status quo and an enemy is supporting thenon-core group

      conditions for internal colonization

    8. Furthermore, if one considers the extent of external support for non-violentmovements across the world, it becomes clear that external involvement for non-core groups around the world is actually a much more prevalent and conse-quential practice than the above statistics indicate

      non core group international intervention is way more common than we think

    9. interethnic cooperation, repression, concessions,and conflict. The important lesson to draw from Jenne’s work for our purposesis the central role that outside support plays in non-core groups’decisions toradicalize their demands

      central role of outside support in radicalizing a non core group

    10. he host state is likely to accommodate the non-core group ifthe ally is strong and the alliance is asymmetrical or exclude and/or assimilate thenon-core group if the ally is weaker and the alliance is symmetrical

      host state will support non group when specific external conditions are met

    11. Non-core group demands can be either territorial or non-territorial. Nonterritorial demands range from legal recognition of the non-coregroup by the host state, to institutionalized political representation at thenational level. Territorial demands range from claims for local autonomy tocalls for independence

      non-core demands: territorial and non-territorial

    12. I refrain from using the term “minority”for a variety of reasons. First, the non-core group category is broader than that of a minority, since it includes aggre-gations of people who are conscious of their difference from the dominantnational type without necessarily being mobilized around this difference.Second, the term “minority”usually refers to “numerically inferior”groups,while the term non-core group does not imply anything about size.

      minority vs non core group is a critical distinction

    13. I follow a statist perspective for the identification of non-core groups. By theterm “non-core group,”I mean any aggregation of individuals that is perceivedas an unassimilated ethnic group (the relevant marker can be linguistic, religious,physical, or cultural) by the ruling political elites of a country at the beginning ofa period analyzed.

      non-core group definition

    14. Turning now to the cases where the power balance is clearly in favor of thehost state, enemy external powers will hesitate to support non-core groupswithin such a state for two reasons: the prospect of a destructive interstatewar will operate as a deterrent

      strong internal states deter supporting secessionist movements within the country

    15. Taking a closer look at state capacity in a relative sense, we find at the oneextreme a situation where the power balance is clearly in favor of the externalpower(s) supporting the non-core group. In this case, a successful secessionistmovement or the capture of the host state is likely.

      how secession can succeed

    16. The term “core group”refers to all the inhabitants of a country who share acommon national type in one or more of the ways just outlined. Often the coregroup forms a demographic majority.

      def of core group

    17. Accommodation refers almost exclusivelyto non-violent policies.30 In order to best understand and distinguish betweenthese policies, however, we must consider the different governmental goals thatlie behind each in specific instances, and not merely whether they involve the useof violence or no

      different goals go into each policy approach

    18. uilding on Weiner, Brubaker has argued that if a nationalminority does not have a national homeland it is more likely to be targeted forassimilation.22 To be sure, Brubaker suggests that he is not interested in pre-diction but from his work we can deduce that a nationalizing state is not likely totarget for assimilation a national minority with a homeland, because the costsare high and the likelihood of success low.

      importance of geography for a minority to play up their national identity

    19. The logic is that they have tocrack down heavily in order to build reputation, discourage, and signal resolveto other potential challengers.17 Treisman’s findings from his study of post-Soviet Russia are in line with Walter’s logic; indeed Treisman suggests thatwhen non-core group elites observe benefits from separatist activities of othergroups, they are likely to follow their example.18 Thus, states with few large,mobilized, and territorially concentrated and potentially secessionist groups aremore likely to pursue exclusionary or assimilationist policies than states withone or none such groups

      states with some large minorities will attempt either exclusionary or assimilationist policies that differ from homogenous states

    20. Research in social psychology provides a mechanism support-ing this hypothesis –namely, that individuals seek to maximize their self-esteem, and that creating a positive social identity (usually at the expense ofsome “other”) is one way of reaching the desired goal.13 In sum, according tothis type of explanation, in cases where the dominant group was previouslydominated by the non-core group, the relations will be conflict-ridden and weshould observe no assimilation or accommodation attempts; on the contrary,exclusion is more likely

      conflict ridden when one group is now free from a previously dominant group

    21. wever, thesesame nationalist sentiments have also led to inter- and intrastate conflict, thedeaths of many civilians, population displacements, and even genocide.5Legitimate authority in modern national states is connected to popular rule,to majorities. Nation-building is the process through which these majorities areconstructed. In this context, foreign powers that want to destabilize a stateattempt to undermine its legitimacy by encouraging and nurturing linguistic,ethnic, or religious differences and regional identities within its borders.

      nationalism is a soft concept and, once divided, the legitimacy of the state can be imperiled

    Annotators

    1. It is worth noting a potential rival explanation for the durability of many revolutionary regimes: communism. A majority (eleven of twenty) of our cases may be described as communist,96 and it could be that communist (or totalitarian) institutions rather than revolutionary origins are the main source of regime durability.

      potential strength special to leftwing revolutions

    2. The destruction of independent power centers and, in many cases, their replacement with state- or party-controlled mass organizations, contributes to authoritarian durability by weakening the structural bases of potential opposition.

      opposition will need to play by the new rules

    3. Due to the cost of defection, elite schisms are less frequent in revo-lutionary autocracies than in other autocracies. Thus, in countries like Vietnam, Cuba, and Mozambique, where revolutionary governments faced enduring military conflict or threat, ruling parties suffered vir-tually no defections for decades.

      schisms are very pricy

    4. But where nascent regimes survive these counterrevolutionary reac-tions, military conflict engenders processes of state building and societal transformation that lay the foundation for long-run authoritarian dura-bility. The violent conflict triggered by efforts to radically transform the domestic and geopolitical status quo generates an enduring perception of existential threat that enhances elite cohesion and contributes to the development of political-military fusion, powerful coercive institutions, and to the destruction of alternative centers of societal power.

      if they can survive, they will be stronger

    5. Most revolutions thus set off armed counterrevolutionary movements that must be defeated if the new regime is to consolidate its hold.53 Such opposition movements are often backed by hostile foreign pow-ers. The Bolsheviks, for example, were plunged into a civil war against White armies backed by British, French, Japanese, and American forces.

      revolutions then must battle the counter revolutionaries

    6. Revolutionary governments do the opposite. Revolutionary elites launch radical policy initiatives aimed at transforming states, societies, economies, and even the regional or international order soon after com-ing to power.

      a radical vision can often help the authoritarian state at the beginning. Jump starting it

    7. Our argument is path dependent: a regime’s origins can set it on a trajectory that becomes difficult to reverse over time.

      path dependence

    8. As we argue below, the powerful party-state complexes that serve as the institutional foundation of revolutionary re-gimes emerged out of counterrevolutionary or external military conflict triggered by the radicalism of new revolutionary governments.

      state complexes are strong when they emerge from external conflict

    9. All the regimes encompassed by our definition are authoritarian, which should not be surprising. Because efforts to carry out radical so-cial transformation attack the vital interests or way of life of powerful domestic actors and large societal groups, they require a level of violence and coercion that is incompatible with liberal democracy.3

      Romania is excluded

    10. Finland in 1918 and Hungary in 1919. In line with gwf and other data sets,27 these two cases, along with all other authoritarian governments that collapsed before the end of the calendar year, are ex-cluded from the sample used in the quantitative analysis.

      is there really a good reason to exclude these from the data set? Sometimes revolutions die and that's a really important consideration, even if it only happened in 2 examples from their data set

    11. It additionally excludes the Eastern European “refolutions” of 1989,19 because those transitions were peace-ful (with the exception of Romania) and left state structures largely intact.20

      can we define romania as a social revolution? If so, its institutions are mired with corruption

    12. Drawing on the classic work of Theda Skocpol, we define a social revolution as the violent overthrow of an existing re-gime from below accompanied by mass mobilization and state collapse, which triggers a rapid transformation of the state and the existing social order.1

      def of social revolution

    13. Third, our analysis highlights the centrality of state institutions rather than party or other pseudodemocratic institutions as a foundation for authoritarian durability.

      institutions obviously don't need to be democratic to have a long shelf life

    14. ut where regimes survive, violent con-flict produces four important legacies: (1) a cohesive ruling elite, (2) a loyal military, (3) a powerful coercive apparatus, and (4) the destruction of rival organizations and alternative centers of power in society

      consequences of when a regime survives

    15. But an examination of the origins and evolution of revolutionary regimes suggests that in many cases, strong party institutions are themselves the product of rev-olutionary origins.

      revolutionary regimes are themselves the productive of revolutionary origins.

    16. volutionary regimes, such as those in Russia, China, Cuba, and Vietnam, endured for more than half a century in the face of strong external pressure, poor economic performance, and large-scale policy failures. The authors develop and test a theory that accounts for such durability using a novel data set of revolutionary regimes since 1900. The authors contend that autocracies that emerge out of violent social revo-lution tend to confront extraordinary military threats, which lead to the development of cohesive ruling parties and powerful and loyal security apparatuses, as well as to the destruction of alternative power centers.

      autocracies that emerge out of violent social revolution tend to confront extraordinary military threats, which leads to the development of a cohesive ruling party with strong security apparatuses

    Annotators

    1. While repression is reprehensible, the debate about authoritarianism and development distracts students of political economy from the real issue: authoritarianism refers to a particular pattern of relationship between rulers and the ruled, but more important is not this pattern but the level of institutionalization of the relationship. It is an institutional structure that gives any state a basis for playing developmental roles effectively, assuming that state leaders at some point are willing to undertake such roles.

      authoritarian is a pattern is not ncessaryily important, rather it is the institutional structure that has given a basis for said authoritarianism

    2. Understanding the importance of state structure in successful developmental-ism is crucial to go beyond the inconclusive debate about the relationship between authoritarianism and development

      debate on authoritarianism and development is counterproductive

    3. n contrast with existing scholarship that stresses colonial lega-cies, I argue that intraelite and elite-mass interactions, especially but not necessarily during state formation, are the primary origin of developmental states in the two cases under examination

      thesis

    4. Elite unity implies unified authority and offers a favorable condition for the creation of a cohesive structure while elite fragmentation poses tremendous obstacles to achieving any stable structure.

      elite unity vs fragmentation can make or break a state

    5. The second dynamic of state formation involves elite-mass engagement patterns that vary from mass incorporation to mass suppression

      mass incorporation vs mass suppression

    6. Compromise means significant concessions in matters of ideology, organization, and material interests. Compromise may entail more than one step or decision. Initial compromises may be followed by more significant ones as certain elites collaborate on the common project of state formation while other groups are marginalized. Compromise is therefore a process of forming a central bloc and eliminating extremes. In the same vein, polarization involves more than one step and means not simply a rejection of compromise by elites, but the process of forming two or more (but not too many) opposing extremes and the elimination of moderate political options

      compromise vs polarization between elites

    7. State formation may protract over centuries as in Western Europe (Tilly, 1990). States may also emerge with a big bang as in many colonized peripheries in the twentieth century.

      big bang versus gradual crystalization

    8. why did developmental states emerge where they did but not elsewhere? This is clearly a historical issue, but it has obvious implications for the contemporary debate about whether the model can be replicated and similar policies may be feasible in other lands with different historical legacies and social conditions.

      debate over origin of the development state is a historical issue

    9. rgue that intraelite and elite-mass interactions, especially, but not necessarily during state formation, are the primary origin of developmental states. The framework suggested here not only fills in a critical theoretical lacuna in the developmental state literature, but also contributes to the debate on the relationship between regime types and development

      intraelite and elite-mass interactons are critical for the formation of developmental states

    Annotators

    1. And the capacity of these in-dustries did as we have seen, increase. Therefore, despite evi-dence of growing external difficulties-which after all were ~t least partially the result of exogenous factors such as the ml crisis-it may well be argued that Brazil's "net" capacity to cope with such problems had increased.

      brazil's net coping capacity improved

    2. olitical structures and policies do weigh heavily in economic outcomes. In Mexico and Brazil, which entered the 195o's with relatively high degrees of state control over populist pressures, GDP and manufacturing con-tinued to grow at very high rates throughout the 195o's.

      1950s success in brazil

    3. In Brazil, perhaps the most industrially integrated of the South American countries, textiles alone accounted for over 20 percent of the value added in manufacturing during the 194o's, and remained until the end of that decade the largest single industrial branchY A similar pattern has been widely documented for each of the other countries.

      brazilian success

    4. and hard-line officers, interested in "development" and "national security" re-spectively. At a more fundamental level of analysis, one finds the evolution of a close working relationship between government officials, foreign managers and investors, and certain national firms benefiting from state subsidies and joint stock arrange-ments-in short, the ruling "trio" constituted by the state, foreign capitalists, and an "associated" domestic bourgeoisie

      almost similar to Shwartz

    5. The ensuing wave of repres-sion-arrests, dismissals, police surveillance, and strict censor-ship-continued unabated during the first three years of the Medici administration (1g6g-1974),

      fifth institutional act

    1. Our data provide additional support for the ideathat the maladaptive behavior of psychopathic individuals may resultfrom attention dysfunctions that prioritize a goal-relevant perspec-tive.

      only prioritize personal goals

    2. Second, although we interpretthe reduced altercentric interference in psychopathic individualsas reflecting differences in their tendency to automatically rep-resent others’mental states, it is possible that psychopathic andnonpsychopathic individuals are just as likely to represent theavatar’s perspective, but that psychopathic individuals morequickly select between the two conflicting perspective represen-tations.

      reduced altercentirc intereference in psychopathic individuals

    3. Replicating previous research, we found a significant maineffect of both perspective [F(1, 105) =5.467, P =0.021, 95% CI(0.001, 0.148)] and consistency [F(1, 105) =248.51, P <0.001, 95%CI (0.607, 0.765)]. Perspective affected response times such thatparticipants were faster to verify the content of their perspective[mean =898.27 ms, 95% CI (861.31, 935.24)] than they were to verifythe content of the avatar’s perspective

      easier to predict when thinking about yourself

    4. Specifically, participants were asked to verify the number of dotsthat either they (self) or the avatar could see. Sometimes the participant andthe avatar could see the same number of dots (consistent trials), and sometimesthey could see different numbers of dots (inconsistent trials).

      comparing dot visuals

    5. We hypothesize that psychopathic individuals may lack thenormal human tendency to automatically take the perspective ofothers.

      hypothesis

    6. mportantly, participantsalso perform worse at reporting their own perspective on thenumber of dots when the avatar’s perspective is different fromtheir own. In this case, participants unintentionally experiencealtercentric interference: they are automatically affected by theavatar’s perspective even when this other perspective hurts theirown performance.

      struggle to assess any outside perspective

    7. uccessful social interaction requires the ability to understandwhat other people are thinking. This ability, often referred to as a “theory of mind”(ToM), helps individuals predict and interpretothers’behaviors, develop meaningful social relationships, com-municate effectively, and engage in appropriate moral reasoning(1–5).

      definition of TOM

    8. Controlled ToM processes are engaged when an individualintentionally considers the perspective of another person, whereasautomatic ToM processes are engaged when an individual uninten-tionally represents the perspective of another person. In a sample ofincarcerated offenders, we find that psychopathic individuals areequally likely to show response interference under conditions ofcontrolled ToM, but lack a common signature of automatic ToMknown as altercentric interference.

      psychopathic individuals have a diminished propensity to automatically think like normal people about other perspectives.

    1. We conclude that psychopaths make the same kind ofmoral distinctions as healthy individuals when it comes toevaluating the permissibility of an action embedded ina moral dilemma. Consequently, these results support thehypothesis that normal social emotional processing doesnot appear necessary for making these kinds of moraljudgments.

      normal social emotional processing does nto appear necessary to make moral judgements

    2. Given these uncertainties,it is perhaps less surprising, and at odds with the existingdata, psychopaths show normal patterns of moral judgmentsfor moral dilemmas. More specifically, though psychopathsshow some of the same emotional deficits as patients withdamage to VMPC, other aspects of their emotions may berelatively preserved, and these may be the most importantwith respect to moral understanding. At present, however,this literature is unclear, with some studies reporting normalrecognition and judgments by psychopaths of basic emotionssuch as anger, fear, sadness and disgust, whereas otherstudies show differences, including evidence of abnormalitiesin brain activation during imaging studies of emotionalprocessing

      research feels inconsistent

    3. 1) since both adults and juveniles received scenar-ios that were designed for children, it is unclear how adultpsychopaths would fare on adult versions

      remain to be scene, why are we relying on children case studies

    4. Second, though psychopaths showeddiminished emotional processing relative to both controlgroups, and even though both delinquent groups differedfrom healthy subjects in their morally inappropriate behav-iors

      psychopaths showed diminished emotional processing

    5. First, like healthy subjects and non-psychopath delinquents, psychopaths judged impersonalmoral actions as more permissible than personal moralactions.

      healthy and psychos judged impersonal moral actions as better than personal ones

    6. Thus,psychopaths were not more likely to endorse the utilitarianoutcome for other-serving, personal dilemmas

      psychopaths were the same as normal people in endorsing utilitarian outcomes

    7. Evaluation of educational level demonstrated a significantdifference between the groups, with offenders having lowerlevels of education than non-offenders, but no differencebetween the two groups of offenders (2[2] ¼12.90;P < 0.05). More importantly, an ANCOVA demonstratedthat there was no significant effect of education onjudgments of either personal or impersonal dilemmas (allP’s > 0.05)

      education not very relevant

    8. Results showed that psychopathicoffenders, unlike the two comparison groups, showed nosignificant increase in cortisol in response to the stressor.Within both the non-psychopathic group and healthycontrols, cortisol levels significantly increased at T1 (beforeadministering the stressor) to T3 (after administering thestressor) as demonstrated by pairwise comparison (allt’s > 2.81; all P’s < 0.01 and all t’s > 3.07; all P’s < 0.01, respec-tively). In contrast, within the psychopathic group therewas no significant increase of cortisol levels between T1and T3 (all t’s < 1.00; all P’s > 0.34); see Cima, Popma,and Nicolson (in preparation) for a more detailed overviewof these data. Thus, based on both their PCL-R scoresand stress reactivity profiles, this psychopathic populationshowed relatively flat emotional responses, consistent withmany other studies

      psychopaths exhibit flatter emotional responses and do not release comparable amounts of cortisol compared to neurotypical people

    9. he following study targets three issues at the core ofcurrent work in moral psychology: (i) To what extent isnormal emotional regulation necessary for making normalmoral judgments, especially in the context of moral dilem-mas where there are no clear, societally-mandated or typicalresponses? (ii) To what extent are the systems that guidemoral judgments dissociable from those that guide moralbehavior? More specifically, do psychopaths show deficitsin both moral knowledge and behavior, in knowledge, orin the link between knowledge and behavior?

      three big questions in psychology can be answered by understanding how psychopaths engage in behavior regulation

    10. suggesting instead that psychopaths understand thedistinction between right and wrong, but do not care about such knowledge, or the consequences that ensue from their morallyinappropriate behavior

      implications of HA

    11. We test an alternative explanation: psychopaths have normal understanding ofright and wrong, but abnormal regulation of morally appropriate behavior.

      alternative hypothesis: psychopaths have normal understandings of right v wrong, they just have wrong assesments of behavior appropriateness

    1. This could suggest that psychopaths not only experi-ence blunted vicariously arousal to others’ pain and reducedfeelings of concern when adopting their perspective, but theymay in fact find the distress of others pleasurable or posi-tively arousing

      psychopaths may find the distress of others arousing

    2. oth studiesreported a reduced response in the aINS and ACC when the chil-dren viewed pictures of others in pain. Furthermore, a negativeassociation between callous traits and the aINS/ACC was found.The fact that individuals with high scores on the PCL-R showed a reduced response when imagining the pain of another suggests aspecific deficit in affective processing in a region considered as acritical hub to integrate salient stimuli and events with visceraland autonomic information (Menon and Uddin, 2010)

      psychopaths have an issue with affective processing of pain relating to others, but not themselves

    3. Psychopaths are characterized by a lack of affective empathy,but there is little evidence that they show a deficit in sensori-motor resonance

      psychopaths still show motor resonance

    4. This findingdoes not support the view that psychopaths do not resonatewhen exposed aversive stimuli such as pain

      psychopaths do respond to aversive stimuli

    5. Interestingly and quite surprisingly, the hemodynamicresponse in aINS and aMCC, regions considered as pivotal in theaffective component of empathy, was highest in high psychopathsduring imagine-self perspective

      psychopaths very sensitive to anything coming close to causing them pain

    6. n healthy participants, activity in this network, whichincludes the aINS, thalamus, aMCC, IFG, and somatosensory cor-tex, has been interpreted as a form of somatosensory resonance,or shared neural representations with the pain of others, provid-ing an implicit intersubjective affective knowledge

      normal people are more likely to be impacted by sensing the pain of others

    7. Functional connectivity analyses seeded in the anterior insularevealed distinct patterns in functional coupling between thelow- and high-psychopathy groups.

      low and high functioning psychopaths are markedly different

    8. during imagine-self perspective, and the reverse was found forimagine-other perspective

      psychopaths only care about their own safety

    9. Additional participants who volunteered for the study but metexclusion criteria were not included. Exclusion criteria were ageyounger than 18 years or older than 55, non-fluency in English,reading level lower than 4th grade, IQ score lower than 80, historyof seizures, prior head injury with loss of consciousness >30 min,current Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders(4th ed.; American Psychiatric Association, 1994) Axis I diagno-sis, lifetime history of a psychotic disorder or psychotic disorderin a first degree relative, or current alcohol or drug use.

      individuals excluded often for drug abuse

    10. ding on past research on perspective taking and empa-thy with healthy participants (Jackson et al., 2006; Lamm et al.,2007; Decety and Porges, 2011) as well as a recent study of pain empathy in criminal psychopaths (Decety et al., 2013), incarcer-ated offenders with different levels of psychopathy on Factors 1and 2 underwent fMRI scanning while watching visual stimulidepicting physical pain. To elicit first- or third-person perspectivetaking (or imagine-self and imagine-other perspectives respec-tively) we explicitly manipulated the task instructions given to theparticipants in the scanner before each block, by asking them tothink of the situations as either occurring to them or to someoneelse.

      experiment

    11. The empathic arousal component, or emotion contagion, devel-ops earlier than the cognitive component, and seems to be hard-wired in the brain with deep evolutionary roots ( Decety andSvetlova, 2012). In addition developmental research has foundthat concern for others emerges prior to the second year of life. Inthese studies, young children are not only moved by others’ emo-tional states, but they make distress and pain attribution in con-junction with their comforting behavior and recognize what thetarget is distressed about (Roth-Hanania et al., 2011). Empathicarousal plays a fundamental role in generating the motivationto care and help another person in distress and depends onlyminimally on mindreading and perspective-taking capacities

      important role of empathetic arousal

    Annotators

    1. Whether individuals with psychopathy understand moral wrongfulness could bear on theinsanity defense in many jurisdictions. The present study cautions that there is insufficientevidence to support insanity defenses based simply on the inability of these individuals tounderstand moral wrongfulness

      insufficient to declare insantiy on psychopaths

    2. However, the present results suggest that an inability to distinguish moral fromconventional wrongs—a lack of distinctively moral knowledge—is not an adequateexplanation for their lack of concern for other

      psychopaths may not be concerned, but they can discern

    3. IQ inparticular—a measure of cognitive ability—explained approximately 54% of the variance intask performance. This effect of IQ might also help to explain the result showing thatinmates as a whole performed less accurately than the university sample. Indeed, inmate IQin this sample (93.3) was lower than that of typical university students. The effect of IQ onmoral categorization accuracy is consistent with previous work conducted on civillycommitted patients with criminal tendencies (O’Kane et al., 1996).

      IQ is a major driver in task performance, so that could be the main culprit.

    4. hese results are consistent with earlier work showing that psychopathic participantsperformed no worse than controls in moral reasoning tasks (Link et al., 1977; Simon et al.,1951).

      affirmed older work saying that psychos are still able to morally reason

    5. In subsequent analyses, IQ strongly correlated with moralaccuracy, r = .52, p < .0001. In order to observe how much variance in performance wasindependently explained by IQ or its possible interaction with psychopathy, we conducted ahierarchical linear regression with (1) IQ, (2) PCL-R, and (3) their product as independentpredictors, and moral accuracy as the dependent measure (see Table 4B). The modelexplained a significant proportion of the variance in moral accuracy (Step 2: R2 = .29, p < .001). All of this variance was attributable to IQ, which, according to a semipartialcorrelation, uniquely explained 53.6% of this variance

      IQ appears a central driver

    6. As a whole, incarcerated participants correctlyclassified 82.6% of the “moral” transgressions as morally wron

      82.6 percent of psychopaths can detect moral transgressions as morally wrong

    7. Undergraduate participants correctly classified 92.5% of the “moral” transgressions asmorally wrong, M = 7.40 (.97). (Moral and conventional accuracy were identical, given thedesign of the task.) In order to determine whether these scores exceeded that of chanceperformance, we first compared moral accuracy to a chance score of 4, using a one-sample t-test. This test confirmed that participants’ moral accuracy was in fact significantly greaterthan chance performance, t(29) =19.23, p < .0001. To examine just how accurate their moraltransgression ratings were, increasingly strict criteria were selected in a series of t-test

      normal people can classify about 92 percent of moral transgressions as morally wrong

    8. The study was composed of a forced-choice categorization task with transgression type(moral vs. conventional) as a within-subjects sorting variable and psychopathy as a between-subjects quasi-independent variable. The primary hypothesis was evaluated by comparingscores within the incarcerated sample. Transgression type was determined by the pilotsample ratings. Moral wrongfulness was defined by acts that society would consider wrongeven if there were no rules, customs, or laws against them (dimension 1 above). For eachtransgression, the presence or absence of harm (dimension 2 above) was also rated in orderto assess the extent to which harm judgments explain variance in moral categorizationaccuracy.

      design of the experiment distringuishes between conventions and moral transgressions

    9. Taken together, if psychopathic individuals can correctly classify moral transgressions, thenthe causes of their antisocial behavior may not be well-explained by failures in moralknowledge or reasoning. Such a result could re-focus attention to other possible sources ofpsychopathic behavior, such as emotional or motivational processes (e.g., Fowles, 1993;Hare, 1978; Latane, 1964; Lykken, 1957). Such a result could also potentially informconceptions of psychopathic legal responsibility by ruling out one common basis forclaiming that psychopaths should be eligible for an insanity defense. Thus, there remains ademand to re-evaluate psychopathic moral knowledge absent of impression management.

      psychopaths may be able to correctly classify moral transgressions. If this is the case, then one would see it logical to proceed with studies around emotional and motivational stimuli around psychopathy

    10. The authors concluded that females with psychopathy can accurately identifymoral norms but they nonetheless fail to utilize this knowledge when doing so wouldcompete with immediate, personal goals. Studies among males have yielded even morestartling results, for example, that psychopathic participants performed better than controlson Kohlberg’s Moral Judgment scale, which challenges respondents to freely justify theirjudgments in various moral dilemmas (Link et al., 1977). These studies lent support to theview that psychopathy is characterized, not by moral knowledge deficits, but perhaps onlyby emotional or motivational abnormalities

      psychopaths can tell what is morally wrong, they just normatively do not seem to care

    11. Currently, the most common legal definition of insanity includes a clause that was intendedto exclude psychopathy (MPC § 4.01(2)); and courts almost never find psychopaths notguilty by reason of insanity, but these facts could change as scientific arguments mount.

      law incapable of responding to advancing psych research

    12. Yet when itcomes to questions of criminal responsibility, it is the nature of their moral reasoning thatmay matter most. This is because, if such capacities are compromised, this fact couldpotentially be used to excuse these defendants’ antisocial behavior on the basis of insanity

      legal utility of figuring out whether psychopaths can discern what is morally wrong

    13. the present study found that total psychopathy score didnot predict performance on the task. Task performance was explained by some individual sub-facets of psychopathy and by other variables unrelated to psychopathy, such as IQ. The authorsconclude that, contrary to earlier claims, insufficient data exist to infer that psychopathicindividuals cannot know what is morally wrong

      psychopathic indviduals may be able to tell what is imorral, this breaks with previous opinions that view that psychopaths cannot view the difference between moral wrongs and other types of wrongs

    1. Then, in the autumn of ig80, the secularist-Islamic regime of Saddam Hussein in neighboring Iraq attacked revolutionary Iran; since the Iraqis perceived Khomeini's regime as weak and internally disorganized, they expected it to fall. What happened with the Jacobins in i 8th-century rev- olutionary France then repeated itself in revolutionary Iran. At first, the foreign invaders made headway, for the remnants of the Shah's military, particularly the army, were indeed disorganized at the command level. But revolutionary Islamic guards poured out to the fronts, and the Iraqi offensives began to come up against fanatically dogged resistance. Islamic fundamentalists and Iranian secular nationalists pulled together, how- ever grudgingly, to resist the common enem

      impact of iran-iraq war

    2. The militant Shi'a clerics of Iran, who seem to be so different from the Vietnamese communists, are another mass-mobilizing and state-building revolutionary elite that has been helped immensely by a facilitating geo- political context and protracted international warfare.33

      geopolitics help justify wars

    3. Vietnamese communists still find it possible to legitimate their leadership through never-ending mobilization of their people for national military efforts.

      constant military mobilization sustains the regime

    4. . In short, U.S. policies since i980, declaredly aimed at "democratiz- ing" Nicaragua, have had the opposite effect; they have undermined ele- ments of pluralism in a postrevolutionary regime and enhanced the na- tionalist credentials of the more authoritarian Nicaraguan Leninists. Still, as of this writing in 1987, it remains possible that shifts in American pol- icy may stop this process of militarization short of full-scale war in Cen- tral America

      us policies creating conditions for the leftwing takeover

    5. Due to the basic geopolitical context, there was never any question of a new regime devoted to mass mobilization for military purposes at any point during the Mexican Revolution. Full-scale war with the United States would obviously have been fatal to any revolutionary leadership, and attempts to export revolution to the south would probably have pro- voked the ire of the northern colossus.

      Mexican revolution and pragmatism

    6. Still, we should note that unlike most other social-revolutionary regimes in the modern world, that of Mexico has never been able to engage in mass mobilization for international war- fare. Nationalist self-assertion has been restricted to state-led economic development, particularly in periods such as the 1930S and 1940s, when the United States was distracted by larger domestic or world crises. Pop- ular political participation has been managed by a corporatist, patronage- oriented party-state that preserves order in economically inefficient way

      economic nationalism yes, but the presence of the US mediates how nationalism will be expressed

    7. The regional context of each revolution also matters: What have been the possibilities for military conflicts with im- mediate neighbors? Have revolutionized third-world nations faced in- vasions by third-world neighbors, or have they been able to invade their neighbors without automatically involving great powers in the conflict?

      regional context of each revolution is critical to how the domestic revolution will pan out

    8. With the exception of the Iranian Revolution of 1977-1979, which was primarily carried out through urban demonstrations and strikes, all third-world social revolutions have depended on at least a modicum of peasant support for their succe

      revolutions usually come from below

    9. From a European continental perspective, the most striking and con- sequential accomplishment of the French Revolution was its ability to launch highly mobile armies of motivated citizen-soldiers, coordinated with enhanced deployment of artillery forces.

      most of the impacts from a revolution can be military

    10. Instead, the differences in the essentially mass- mobilizing and authoritarian outcomes and accomplishments of the French, Russian, and Chinese revolutions are in large part attributable to the international geopolitical contexts in which the conflicts of these rev- olutions played themselves out. They are also attributable to the political relationships established, during and immediately after the revolutionary interregnums, between state-building leaderships and rebellious lower classe

      wage war capacity increased after revolutions + all outcomes different due to geopolitical contexts

    11. (a) the centralized, semi-bureaucratic administrative and military organizations of the old regimes disintegrated due to combinations of in- ternational pressures and disputes between monarchs and landed com- mercial upper classes, and (b) widespread peasant revolts took place against landlord

      social revolutions caused by (1) disintigration of ancien regime services and (2) widespread peasant revolts

    12. se. Rather, the French, Russian, and Chinese revolutions, despite important variations, displayed striking sim- ilarities of context, cause, process, and outcomes. All three classic social revolutions occurred in large, previously inde- pendent, predominantly agrarian monarchical states that found them- selves pressured militarily by economically more developed competitors on the international scene

      French, Russian, and Chinese revolutions occured in agrarian monarchical states that were falling behind their neighbors

    13. Whether "communist" or not, I argue, revolutionary elites have been able to build the strongest states in those countries whose geopolitical circumstances allowed or required the emerging new re- gimes to become engaged in protracted and labor-intensive international warfare

      protracted and labor-intensive warfare produces more succesful revolutionary regimes that build strong states

    14. Whether we in the liberal-democratic West like to acknowledge it or not, the authoritarian regimes brought to power through revolutionary transformations from the French Revolution of the late i 8th century to the Iranian Revolution of the present- have been democratizing in the mass-mobilizing sense.

      iranian revolution democratizing in the mass-mobilizing sense

    15. There is a straightforward reason why this should be true: the types of organizations formed and the political ties forged between revolutionary vanguards and supporters (in the course of defeating other elites and con- solidating the new regime's state controls) can readily be converted to the tasks of mobilizing resources, including dedicated officers and soldiers, for international warfare.

      types of organizations formed in revolutions can easily mobilize resources and connect leaders with citizens

    16. Yet I would argue that the task which revolutionized regimes in the modern world have per- formed best is the mobilization of citizen support across class lines for protracted international warfar

      task which revolutionized regimes in the modern world was the mobilization of civilian support

    17. Briefly put, this happens because during revolutionary interregnums competition among elites for coercive and authoritative control spurs cer- tain leadership groups to mobilize previously politically excluded popular forces by means of both material and ideological incentives

      revolutionary interregnums force popular involvement

    18. odernization theorists and Marxians both analyze revolution- ary transformations primarily in relation to long-term socioeconomic change. These scholars also highlight the contributions of certain revo- lutions to liberalism or to democratic socialism that is, to "democracy" understood in opposition to authoritarian state powe

      modernization vs marxist schools

    1. Second, we show that theopportunity for free choice is associated withincreased activity in regions implicated in process-ing rewards, as well as with higher reportedsatisfaction.

      processing rewards

    2. In summary, we find that three very differentthings—monetary payoffs to oneself, observing acharity get money, and a warm-glow effect relatedto free choice—all activate similar neural sub-strates. This result supports arguments for acommon “neural currency”of reward (25–29)and shows that this model can be applied not justto choice over money, risk, and private con-sumption goods, but also to more abstract policychoices involving taxation and charitable giving(12).

      common "neural currency" of altruistic deeds

    3. lso,reported satisfaction was higher for voluntary thanfor mandatory transfers after controlling for payoffs(P < 0.065 for the complete design; P < 0.001 using the cells involving tradeoffs, purple in Fig.1B). The pure altruism motive for giving, alongwith the story about adding choices describedabove, would imply that there should be nomandatory-voluntary differences after controllingfor the payoff effects. Thus, our results suggest thatboth the increased payoffs and the ability to chooselead to increased neural activity and satisfaction

      increased payoffs and the abilit to choose lead to increased satisfaction

    4. An important question, then, is to what degreethe observed higher activation comes from theability to make a choice and to what extent it resultsfrom the differences in payoffs from that choice

      question about is voluntary more attractive

    5. 10% higher for voluntary than for themandatory transfers (P < 0.01, see Fig. 2B and table S2) (16).

      slight more satisfaction from voluyntary

    6. Altruists gave money nearly twice asoften as egoists (58% versus 31%, P = 0.015).This supports the existence of a purely altruisticmotive: The larger a person's neural response toincreases in the public good, no matter thesource, the more likely they will give voluntarily.

      altruistis will give voluntarily no matter the means

    7. This isthe first evidence we know of demonstrating thatmandatory taxation for a good cause can produceactivation in specific brain areas that have been tiedto concrete, individualistic rewards

      individualistic rewards sensations can come from mandatory charity donation

    8. To test for the pure altruism and warm-glowmotives, we used functional magnetic resonanceimaging while subjects played a dictator game.Subjects received $100 and then made decisionsabout whether or not to give money to a localfood bank. They also observed mandatory, tax-like transfers of their money to the food bank(Fig. 1, A and B) (16). The behavioral results inthis experiment are consistent with economictheory and are similar to those reported in earliereconomic experiments (17–19). As shown in Fig.2A, increases in the amounts going to the charityand decreases in the cost to the giver both in-creased the likelihood that a voluntary transferwas accepted. Self-reported satisfaction with thetransaction followed the same pattern in both the voluntary and the mandatory conditions (Fig. 2B).

      experiment methods

    9. This reward from giving has been termed “warmglow”(3, 4). If givers were driven exclusively bythe warm-glow motive, they should derive satisfac-tion from making a voluntary gift, rather than fromthe increase in the level of the public good itself

      warm glow=donations must be voluntary

    10. some satisfaction even when public goods aresupplied through mandatory taxation, because, bythis account, people care only about how much ofthe public good is provided and not about theprocess by which the transfer occurs

      pure altruism implies taxes should give u moral satisfaction

    11. Individuals with such amotive receive satisfaction from increases in apublic good, such as the provision of basic servicesto the needy. This altruistic concern provides amotive to give, but there is also an incentive to keepmoney for oneself, because the cost of such charityis entirely paid by the giver, whereas the benefits arespread out over all those people who care about theneedy.

      benefits are diffuse

    12. Consistent with pure altruism,we find that even mandatory, tax-like transfers to a charity elicit neural activity in areas linked toreward processing. Moreover, neural responses to the charity's financial gains predict voluntarygiving. However, consistent with warm glow, neural activity further increases when people maketransfers voluntarily. Both pure altruism and warm-glow motives appear to determine the hedonicconsequences of financial transfers to the public good.

      tax-like transfers to charity still elicit reward processing

    Annotators

    1. Collectively, evidence of activation within this suite of brain regionssupports the proposal that these neural pathways provide an interfacebetween motivational states and behavioral action (Packard andKnowlton, 2002). In other words, the caudate, VTA and sgACC appearto be regulating empathically biased goal-directed behavior (Luo et al.,2011), serving to motivate the subject to respond to the distress ofanother (Preston, 2013), even if it is at a cost to the self.

      mechanism behind costly morality

    2. In line with the caregiving model, our findingsprovide evidence that individuals' readiness to help others is drivenmore by their trait levels of other-oriented empathic concern than bytheir trait levels of personal distress

      other-oriented empathetic concern is more powerful

    3. On the other hand, observing theconsequences of progressively prosocial decisions (larger amounts ofMoney Given-Up) was associated with greater activity in OFC and theposterior portion of the dlPFC (on the border between BA 9 and 44)(Fig. 2A, Table 11) —regions known to support reward valuation(O'Doherty et al., 2001), and which are necessary for top-down process-ing (Ochsner and Gross, 2005; Preston, 2013)

      we reward ourselves for progressively more prosocial decisions

    4. Al-though we found no behavioral evidence that trait Personal Distresscorrelated with costly altruism, the equivalent analysis with PersonalDistress scores entered as a second level covariate revealed increasingactivity in the ACC (

      personal dsitress

    5. In line with the empathy–altruismhypothesis, subjects' trait Personal Distress scores were not signifi-cantly correlated with Money Given-Up and the effect size estimatewas small (r = .16, p = .53), while trait Empathic Concern didpositively correlate with Money Given-Up with a large effect size(r = 0.53, p = .02; [Fig. 2B])

      empathetic concern more significant a factor

    6. revealed that sub-jects reported being distressed at watching another in pain (mean 8.2SD ± 1.3). We shouldalso notethat only onesubjectselected theoption‘no shock’more than once; but even this subject choose to forgo themoney and administer ‘no shock’on only six of the 20 trials.

      most were distressed at seeing others in pain

    7. Altogether, we tested nine different regions of interestthat are outlined in the caregiving model to either inhibit or facilitatehelping behavior.

      tested 9 different regions of interest

    8. After makinga selection,subjects saw a 3 s display of their choice be-fore experiencing an 8 s anticipation phase —during which subjectswere told their choice was being transmitted over the internal networkto theother testing lab where the Receiver was connected to the electricstimulation generator. Following this anticipation period, subjectsviewed a 4 s video of the stimulation being administered (Videoevent) to the Receiver, or no stimulation if they had opted to spendthe full £1 permitted on a given trial. The Decider was able to see theentire face and body of the Receiver responding to the shock. TheVideo event was in fact pre-recorded footage of real shocks beingadministered to the Receiver, pre-rated by an independent group so asto be matched for shock level and corresponding pain intensity

      shock pain experiment

    9. we hypothesized that if we found evidence that em-pathic sub-processes rely on separate neural circuitry, it would supportthe notion that these two psychological states differentially motivatealtruistic action. If this were indeed the case, the care-giving model(Preston, 2013) proposes that a pattern of avoidant (i.e. selfish or nohelping) behavior would likely engage the dACC, amygdala, andperiaqueductal gray (PAG) —regions key for processing conflict andwhich have been shown to correspond with negative emotions andavoidant maternal expressions (Numan, 2006). In contrast, a candidatenetwork for processing behavioral approach patterns, are the dopaminerich mesolimbic regions (Preston, 2013), which include the ventral teg-mental area (VTA), caudate, and Nucleus Accumbens (NAcc) —areasthat are tied to altruistic giving

      hypothesis

    10. Evidence of such vicariously experienced distress has also beendemonstrated at the neural level. A decade of brain imaging studieshas led to a replicable neural circuitry that is activated in a variety ofempathic situations (Singer et al., 2004; Lamm et al., 2011), andincludes the bilateral anterior insular (AI) and dorsal anterior cingulatecortices (dACC) —key regions in the brain's response to physical pain(Singer et al., 2004; Lamm et al., 2007; Akitsuki and Decety, 2009).This reliable ‘empathy for pain’network illustrates that the experiencesof self and other pain are intimately associated —if you suffer, I too suf-fer(Decetyet al., 2008).

      experience of self and pain are tied together

    11. are we primarily driven to help at a cost to ourselves becausewe experience other oriented feelings of concern, or mainly to alleviateour own discomfort when seeing another in pain

      the first, not the second

    12. his is supported by a theory suggesting that altruistic be-havior –helping others at a cost to the self (de Waal, 2008) –is a func-tion of the desire to minimize one's own discomfort when observingothers in pain (Cialdini et al., 1987). Alternatively, the empathy–altru-ism hypothesis proposes that ‘other-oriented’empathic emotions,such as sympathy, are better predictors of altruistic behavior

      altruistic behavior is a process of discomfort at observing others in pain is challenged in this study

    13. Here we explore the relationshipbetween costly altruism and these two sub-processes of empathy, specifically drawing on the caregivingmodel to test the theory that trait empathic concern (e.g. general tendency to have sympathy for another) andtrait personal distress (e.g. predisposition to experiencing aversive arousal states) may differentially drive altru-istic behavior. We find that trait empathic concern –and not trait personal distress –motivates costly altruism,

      costly altruism is motivated by a general tendency to have sympathetic feelings for another

    Annotators

    1. A limitation of the present study is that it included only asmall number of participants. Replication with a greater num-ber of subjects will increase our confidence in the generaliz-ability of these findings

      issue of small sample size

    2. emotion acts as a gain anteced-ent to moral judgment by alerting the individual to the moralsalience of a situation and provides evidence for the pervasiverole of affect in moral cognition

      emotion acts as a "gain atecedent" is confirmed

    3. we demonstrate for the first time howintention understanding in the right pSTS (62 ms after stimulusonset) and then affective processing occurs in very early stages ofmoral cognition processing

      affective processing occurs in very early stages of moral congition processing

    4. The early engagement of the right amygdala/temporal poleand vmPFC evoked by the perception of intentional harmfulactions suggests that affective processes precede cognitiveevaluative processes

      affective precedes cognitive evaluation processes

    5. The perception of intentional harmwas associated with better (90% vs. 71%) and faster reactiontimes for intentional harm compared with accidental harm(P 0.05),

      perception of intentional harm was more reflexive of a response

    6. o determine the timing and order of component processesimplicated in moral cognition and whether affective processingoccurs during moral evaluations or antecedent to them, weused high-density ERPs to examine the spatiotemporal dynam-ics of the neural processing evoked by the perception of visualmorally laden scenarios.

      method

    7. During the IIT, participants watched a series of three-frame videoclips that were presented centrally on a monitor screen, as in aprevious fMRI study (Decety et al. 2012). The first frame (T1) fromthe video clip was 500 ms long and displayed an establishing scene;the second frame (T2) was a 700-ms frame displaying either anintentional harm or an accidental harm, followed by a third 1,000-msframe (T3) confirming the intentional or accidental harm.

      three-frame video clip technique kept timing brief and stressed the intentionality/accidental nature of things

    8. The results of that study showed that the perception ofintentional harm vs. accidental harm was associated withincreased signal in the amygdala, periaqueductal gray, insula,vmPFC, and right pSTS/TPJ. High-density ERPs can identifypatterns of communication between regions that contrast anal-yses may not detect, and such methods are necessary toadvance of knowledge of the neuroscience of morality

      intentionally is a key factor in how we judge things

    9. One serious limitation of a majority of previous neuroimag-ing studies is that the results rely only on subtraction logic intheir designs, which is based on the a priori assumption thatone computational process can be added to a preexisting set ofprocesses without affecting them, assuming that there are nointeractions among the different components of a given task.

      limits to previous studies

    10. Our data strongly support the notion that intentionality isthe first input to moral computations. They also demonstrate thatemotion acts as a gain antecedent to moral judgment by alerting theindividual to the moral salience of a situation and provide evidence forthe pervasive role of affect in moral sensitivity and reasoning

      notion of intentionality is the first input to moral computations and emotion acts as a gain atecedent to judgements

    11. Neuroscience research indicates that moral reasoning is underpinnedby distinct neural networks including the posterior superior temporalsulcus (pSTS), amygdala, and ventromedial prefrontal cortex, whichsupport communication between computational systems underlyingaffective states, cognitions, and motivational processes

      moral reasoning involves the nexus of several communication and computational systems

    Annotators

    1. Another limitation is that none of our scenarios involved friends, who may or may not be perceived like kin. Therefore, whether there are similar, quantitatively different, or qualitatively different obligations to socially close but unrelated other people remains unknown (but see

      are friends like family at some point?